YURI BOREV
AESTHETICS
AESTHETICS: THE AXIOLOGY OF UNIVERSAL HUMAN VALUES
Aesthetics: The Branch of Knowledge Dealing
with the Aesthetic Diversity of Life and Art
THE BEAUTIFUL
The Beautiful in the History of Aesthetics
Admiring a beautiful woman, Boris Pasternak said that to fathom the
secret of her charm is tantamount to solving the riddle of life. The
secret of beauty is the secret of life.
On a spring day of 1848, Heinrich Heine, who was gravely ill, walked
out into the sunlit streets of Paris adorned with first greenery.
Fighting weakness, he made his way to the Louvre and stopped
before the Venus of Milo. The poet came to that treasurehouse of
art to take his leave of life. To part with life meant for him to part
with beauty.
The secret of beauty has puzzled man for centuries. Debates
concerning it have never stopped throughout the history of
mankind.
Ancient civilisations have produced objects which give an idea of our
ancestors' understanding of the world and their philosophical and
aesthetic views. One of the world's oldest civilisations was that
created by the Sumerians. As far back as in the 25th century B.C.,
they had a written language. A text dating back to that period
contains one of the earliest disputes about the problem which even
now has not been solved by aesthetics: the relationship between the
beautiful and the useful. The text, called Summer and Winter, or
Enlil Chooses the Patron of Peasants, tells about Enlil, the Air God,
who decided to bring affluence to the earth and created two
brothers, Emesh (Summer) and Enten (Winter). Each brother
claimed to be the more handsome, and the father settled the
argument by naming the more useful as the more beautiful:
The waters which bring life to all countries are the charge of Enten,
The tiller of land among the Gods, who produces all.
Emesh, my son, how can you compare yourself to your brother Enten!
The aesthetic doctrine expounded here is a forerunner of Socrates'
idea that the more useful is the more beautiful.
The Sumerian poem Inanna Chooses a Husband also identifies the
utilitarian and the beautiful. Utu, the Sun God, pleads with his sister
Inanna to marry Dumuzi, the God of Shepherds. Inanna rather
prefers Enkimda, the God of Land-Tillers, "who grows grain in
abundance". "But how is he better than I?" inquires Dumuzi and
argues that he does more good than Enkimda, who can give only
grain and peas. Finally, Inanna chooses the God of Shepherds, who
can benefit people in more ways by giving them sweet cheese, cream,
skins and wool, i.e. provide them with food, clothes and footwear.
In the text, the economic role of cattle-breeding and its singular
usefulness account for the greater beauty of the God of Shepherds
and, consequently, the greater weight of his claim to becoming a
member of the family of the Sun God by marrying Inanna.
Similarly, the ancient Egyptian civilisation left no treatises devoted
solely to aesthetics. But scattered among its literary works, hymns
to gods and pharaohs' life stories are many profound theoretical
ideas on the nature of art and the aesthetic qualities of life. An
ancient Egyptian papyrus glorifying the beauty of the Nile says:
The ruler of the fishes, the leader of the birds,
Creating barley, creating emmer,
He brings feasts to the temples.
If he slows down, all breathing stops
And all people grow pale,
Sacrifices to gods are destroyed,
And millions of people perish....
When he rises, the earth rejoices
And everything living is filled with joy,
The teeth begin to laugh....
Bringing bread, abundant in food,
Creating all beauty....
This hymn to the Nile written in the period of the Middle Kingdom
treats beauty as a product of life and the source of its continuation
and its boons. Egyptians believed that beauty was life. The hymn
to Aton, the Sun King, says,
You give life to the hearts by your
Beauty, which is life.
In antiquity, man's approach to the world was still quite
uncomplicated; the aesthetic and the practical were not completely
divorced, and therefore every relationship of man with the world can
be considered aesthetic.
Classical Greek aesthetics was part of an undivided body of
knowledge. Individual sciences had not yet formed independent
branches of the single tree of human knowledge. Every characteristic
of the universe had grains of aesthetic appreciation. The very idea
of the world was essentially aesthetic. The first natural philosophers
considered the aesthetic and the cosmological as one: the beautiful
was a universal quality of beauty, the universal harmony and beauty
of cosmos (the word means the universe, the world, adornment,
apparel, beauty, order, harmony; it is no chance that the word
cosmetics is derived from the same root).
Natural philosophers maintained that the world and its beauty were
objective reality, and the idea has won many adherents among
theorists in later ages. The Pythagoreans regarded the world as a
well-organised system, "the whole heaven ... is ... a musical scale and
a number". The interpretation of the very essence of the universe as
resting on the combination of these two elements lies at the roots
of the theoretical tradition of "measuring harmony by algebra",
which has eventually led to modern structural methods used in the
study of art.
Developing the problem of acoustics in music, the Pythagoreans
for the first time ever implemented the idea of a mathematical
approach to beauty. They discovered the dependence of the musical
intervals on certain arithmetic ratios of lengths of string: at the same
tension, 2:1 giving the octave, 3:2 the fifth and 4:3 the fourth.
Beauty is harmonious, and harmony appears where there is
inequality, the unity of diversity. In the presence of equality and
absence of contradiction, harmony is unnecessary, but where the
opposites are mixed in equal proportion, there is well-being and
health. Musical harmony is a particular case of universal harmony,
its expression through sound. Beauty is the measure of harmony
and reality of existence, the measure of concord with cosmos.
The Pythagoreans developed the idea of the harmony of spheres.
Planets were supposed to be surrounded by air and fastened to lucid
spheres. The intervals between the spheres relate as the intervals of
the tones in the octave. The motion of the planets produces sounds
whose pitch depends on the speed of the motion. But human ear is
unable to perceive the universal harmony of the spheres. This
fantastical theory reflects the naive and cheerful idea of the Universe
as a gloriously sounding orchestra.
In the opinion of Heraclitus, harmony was not a static balance but
motion and dynamics. In his teaching, the central and most powerful
element is fire. He compared the life and destiny of all living beings
to the flame which consumes everything and turns it into ashes thus
making birth possible again, after which death will follow once more.
The beauty of life is the beauty of struggle, the beauty of perpetual
death and perpetual formation and resurrection from the ashes in
a multitude of new forms. Beauty is the nature of fire woven from
contradictions and straining into the future. Contradiction is the
source of harmony and the condition of the existence of beauty:
that which diverges comes together; the most perfect harmony
emerges from opposition. Straining apart, the two points of the
drawn bow or a lyre produce coordinated action. Heraclitus saw the
structure of the beautiful in the unity of conflicting opposites. The
image of the bow was a theoretical model of the dialectical structure
of harmony, historically very accurate: the bow was the forerunner
and the first source of musical sound; all stringed instruments can be
traced back to it.
For the first time in the history of aesthetics, Heraclitus discussed
perception of beauty which, in his opinion, can be understood not
through calculation or abstract thinking but through contemplation.
How can one measure fire, that all-consuming element, which is
never the same? According to Heraclitus, to grasp the essence of fire,
i.e. beauty, the thinking and contemplating individual has to possess
a highly delicate instrument – the ability to think dialectically, which
is the quality of thought that likens it to fire. For Heraclitus, to
understand the essence of life and the nature of beauty means to
reveal the controversial character of existence, birth and death,
struggle and harmony.
Empedocles, another Greek materialist, believed that the world was
made up of four protoelements: fire, air, earth, and water. They
are united by love, which produces harmony and beauty, and divided
by animosity, which is the source of chaos and ugliness. The teaching
of Empedocles is marked by a unity of cosmogony and aesthetics.
It also contains the idea of evolutionism. The initial period in the
development of the living nature was the time when only disjointed
organs existed – arms without shoulders, eyes without a face, etc.
Later, these organs began to combine, accidentally and chaotically.
The epoch of monsters was in, whole beings who were devoid of
harmony and beauty in the combination of their parts. Only the
contemporary epoch has produced animals and people who were
sensibly and harmoniously organised. The evolution of living nature
was for Empedocles the aesthetic evolution of the world, the process
of the emergence of beauty and harmony.
Democritus advanced the theory of measure and developed the
doctrine of hedonism: life should be enjoyable; one should enjoy
only that which is beautiful, and in moderation. Not any pleasure
should be pursued but only that which has at least an element of
the beautiful. To him who has become immoderate the most pleasant
may become most unpleasant.
Plato's dialogues contain a comprehensive and profound analysis
of the beautiful. In the Greater Hippias, the question he poses is
not What is beautiful?' but 'What is beauty?' The interlocutors are
Hippias and Socrates; the latter tries to show the former how to
reach the correct solution to a problem.
Socrates: "What is beauty?" Hippias: "I assure you, Socrates, if
I must speak the truth, that a beautiful maiden is a beauty." This
reply clarifies the point of departure in the analysis of the beautiful:
its concrete quality. However, beauty is not only concrete and
individual but is a characteristic of whole categories of phenomena.
Socrates stresses this idea saying, "Is not a beautiful mare a beauty
... but what about a beautiful lyre ... what about a beautiful pot? ...
Is not that a beauty?" He gradually brings Hippias to the conclusion
that the beautiful is something individual inherent in a multitude,
something concrete which is nevertheless universal. To Hippias, it
seems awkward to mention a beautiful woman and a beautiful pot
in a single breath, but Socrates draws his attention to the relativity
of the beautiful: to determine the measure of the object's beauty,
a comparison with other objects is necessary. Socrates quotes
Heraclitus, who said, "...the most beautiful of apes is ugly compared
with the human race.... The wisest of men, when compared to a god,
will appear but an ape in wisdom and beauty and all else".
In an attempt to find absolute beauty, Hippias suggests that this
may be a property of gold, "For I suppose we all know that if
anything has gold added to it, it will appear beautiful when so
adorned even though it appeared obly before." But Socrates objects
that Phidias has carved a beautiful sculpture of Athena not out of gold but of ivory. Moreover, to supplement a clay pot, a fig spoon is beautiful while a gold one is ugly. But in that case the beautiful
is the humdrum routine, the normal, the common, the age-old and
sanctified by tradition? Hippias says, "Then I maintain that always,
everywhere, and for every man it is most beautiful to be rich,
healthy, honoured by the Greeks, to reach old age and, after burying
his parents nobly, himself to be borne to the tomb with solemn
ceremony by his own children." Socrates however notes that this
does not embrace the exceptional: heroes born fron immortal gods
or the gods themselves.
Finally, a definition is worked out: the beautiful is that which is
beneficial, useful and has power to produce something good. But
Socrates reminds his opponent, however, that there are things which
are quite useful for perpetrating an evil deed, and these are far
removed from the beautiful. Is not then the beautiful that which
is useful for a good deed, i.e. the useful itself? This supposition,
introducing a utilitarian element into the definition of beauty, is
also rejected. "It looks as if the view which a little while ago we
thought the finest result of our discussions, the view that the
beneficial, and the useful, and the power to produce something
good, is beautiful, is in fact wrong...."1 A new, sensualist approach
to the beautiful emerges, which explains the significance of the latter
as a source of pleasure: "Beauty is the pleasant which comes through
the senses of hearing and sight", while the designation "beautiful"
is denied "to that which is pleasant according to the other senses,
that is, the senses which have to do with food, and drink, and sexual
intercourse, and all such things". Further on, Plato draws a line
between physical and spiritual beauty; using Socrates as his
mouthpiece, he also poses very reasonable questions: what about
brilliant actions and laws? Hearing and vision have nothing to do
with the pleasure one derives from these.
Further still, he tries to blend the utilitarian, the sensualist and the
ethical definitions: "beauty is that which is both useful and powerful
for some good purpose". But Plato makes a distinction between the
good and the beautiful. His Socrates says, "Then most certainly
beauty is not good nor the good beautiful".
The dispute between Hippias and Socrates does not evolve a final
definition of beauty, which does not at all mean that it was
theoretically fruitless. In the course of it, a comprehensive and
dialectical analysis of the beautiful is made, while the final result of
the dispute is summed up by its last phrase: "All that is beautiful
is difficult."
In Philebus, Plato says, "I do not mean by beauty of form such
beauty as that of animals or pictures, which the many would suppose
to be my meaning; but... understand me to mean straight lines and
circles, and the plane or solid figures which are formed out of them
by turning-lathes and rulers and measures of angles; for these I affirm
to be not only relatively beautiful, like other things, but they are
eternally and absolutely beautiful, and they have peculiar
pleasures..." Plato looks for beauty in solids, in the quality of being
proportionate. In the final analysis, Plato's beauty is a specific
aesthetic idea man can grasp only in a state of obsession or
inspiration, through the memories the immortal soul has of the time
when it has not yet inhabited the mortal body but existed in the
world of ideas.
Noting the beauty of a concrete object, Plato listens as it were to that
which emerges in the soul of man in the presence of beauty. He was
the first to treat the beautiful as the product of man's aesthetic and
spiritual relation to the object and not as an innate property of
objects. This interpretation of the beautiful points to its suprasensual
nature. However, Plato sees the source of this quality of the
beautiful not in social life or history but in the primacy of the
spiritual.
The most valuable part of Plato's doctrine is its detailed
characteristic of beauty and the idea that aesthetic experience has
features which are all its own: contemplation of the beautiful is the
source of a number of unique "pleasures".
Hegel noted in his lectures on the history of philosophy that the
very trend of Plato's discussion concerning the beautiful and its
qualities shows that Plato gave a dialectical interpretation of the
beautiful as the product of man's spiritual, specifically human
approach to the world.
As distinct from Plato, Aristotle regarded the beautiful not as an
objective idea but as an objective property of things, saying that "beauty is a matter of size and order". "To be beautiful, a living
creature, and every whole made of parts, must not only present a
certain order in its arrangement of parts, but also to be of a certain
definite magnitude." Here, Aristotle gives a structural characteristic
of beauty stressing the size, proportions and order as the elements
of the beautiful. Developing the Pythagorean tradition, Aristotle
maintained that these properties can be assessed with the help of
mathematics.
Aristotle suggested the principle of comparability of man and a
beautiful object, saying that beauty is "impossible either 1) in a very
minute creature, since our perception becomes indistinct as it
approaches instantaneity; or 2) in a creature of vast size ...as in that
case, instead of the object being seen all at once, the unity and
wholeness of it is lost to the beholder".
According to Aristotle, the beautiful should be neither too small nor
too large. This seemingly naive idea is nevertheless that of a genius.
Beauty becomes a measure, and the measure of all things is man.
It is in comparison with man that the beautiful object should not be
out of proportion.
Aristotle's doctrine of beauty theoretically corresponded to the
humanitarian character of the art of classical antiquity. As distinct
from a pyramid, the Parthenon is neither too small nor too large;
it is small enough not to overwhelm man but large enough to convey
the greatness of the Athenians who created it.
In the Middle Ages, the dominating doctrine was that of the divine
origin of beauty (Thomas Aquinas, Tertullian, Francis of Assisi):
animating the inert matter, god renders it aesthetic. Sensual beauty
was looked upon as sinful; enjoyment of it was prohibited.
The humanists of the Renaissance (Leonardo da Vinci, Shakespeare)
glorified the beauty of nature and the joy it gives man. They
regarded art as a mirror used by the artist to reflect nature.
The aestheticians of classicism (Boileau) reduced the beautiful to
the refined; not all flowering and luxuriant nature was considered
beautiful but only the trimmed and groomed part of it, like, for
instance, Versailles. Classicists insisted that the sublime object of
art was beauty in social life seen as goodness and state expediency.
French Enlighteners (Voltaire, Diderot et al) expanded the realm of
the beautiful, once more granting it to life in all its manifestations.
For them, beauty was an innate property of nature itself, like weight,
colour, size, etc.
The German classical aesthetics introduced a number of dialectical
ideas into the notion of the nature of the beautiful. Kant said that
beauty was an object of a disinterested relationship. Hegel's approach
was the historic one. He saw the beautiful as a stage in the evolution
of the Universal Spirit (the Absolute Idea). In the course of it, the
Spirit is harmoniously united with the material form; the idea finds
a complete and adequate expression in the form, and that is
beautiful. Such state was attained by the Absolute Idea in the art
of classical antiquity (Ancient Greece). For Hegel, beauty lies in the
realm of art.
Nikolai Chernyshevsky, the Russian aesthetician, maintained that
beauty is life as it should be. His doctrine treats beauty
materialistically. At the same time, it bears a stamp of
anthropologism: Chernyshevsky thought that beauty in nature
anticipated man.
In the late 19th-early 20th century, aesthetics in Western Europe
was dominated by subjective idealism. It maintained that in the
process of aesthetic perception man spiritualises the aesthetically
neutral world, making it emanate beauty. Only man can introduce
beauty into nature, which, taken by itself, lies beyond the realm of
the beautiful or the ugly and is outside aesthetics, morals or logic.
Nature is beautiful only if aesthetic perception has made it so. From
the aesthetic point of view, it is rich only in that which has been lent
to it by art.
Paradigms of Theoretical Perception of Beauty
Each of the numerous concepts of the beautiful advanced in the
history of aesthetics leans towards one of the theoretical models
which have been discussed above. In other words, they can all be
reduced to five paradigms.
Paradigm 1 (Plato, Tertullian, Thomas Aquinas, Francis of Assisi,
Hegel): beauty is a manifestation of god (or the Absolute Idea)
in concrete objects and phenomena.
Paradigm 2: life is aesthetically neutral, the source of its beauty is
in the soul of man (Ch. Lalo, Theodor Lipps, E. Meumann), it
emerges when man lends or loans (Jean Paul), emotionally penetrates
(B. Croce), or projects (N. Hartmann) his inner wealth to life; beauty
is a result of the intentional (purposeful, active, conscious)
perception of the object by the subject (phenomenologists).
Paradigm 3 (Socrates, Aristotle, Chernyshevsky): beauty appears
when the various aspects of life are brought into correlation with
man as the measure of beauty or with his practical needs, ideals and
ideas of life as it should be.
Paradigm 4 (French materialists): beauty is the natural property of
objects and phenomena.
Paradigm 5 (Soviet aestheticians): beauty is a quality of objectively
existing phenomena with their natural properties which have been
involved by social production and human activity into the sphere of
man's interests and acquired a positive value for man as a race.
They have been spiritualised and humanised by labour becoming the
realm of freedom, i.e. the field where man is the master of life.
Let us analyse the principal theoretical ideas of this fundamentally
new approach to the problem of the beautiful.
We perceive the harmony and symmetry in the world around us as
beauty. They lie, as it were, in the very foundation of matter.
Particles and antiparticles in the microcosm form the basis of the
structure of an atom. Antiparticles are mirror reflections of particles.
This essential property of matter – the harmony and symmetry of its
structure – is repeated in a leaf of a tree, the build of various animals,
and the human face. This essential property of the world, its material
nature, the overall connection and interaction of its phenomena,
comprises the natural basis of the beautiful. With the infinite variety
and multitude of phenomena, they are correlated and linked with
each other by millions of ties, and are adjusted to each other, and can
therefore become the objects of study. Exploring the world, man
is naturally guided by its properties and the laws governing it. The
interaction of nature and society, which is the result of labour and
production, creates beauty as the world's objective quality, as
the value of its objects for humanity and as a sphere where man has
mastered the world and is therefore free.
The first objects of man's aesthetic relation to the world were the
tools he used. Man derived pleasure from a well-made tool whose
shape suited its function and purpose. Labour itself became a source
of aesthetic enjoyment which aroused man's pride, joy and
amazement at his own capacity for creating. As human activities
grew more varied, the range of aesthetic values also expanded. Man
began to aesthetically appreciate nature, himself and the society
he lived in. That which for a tribe was useful, desirable and
important, that which symbolised power and wealth was considered
beautiful. Labour is older than art. Utilitarian views were the first
to be acquired by man, and it is only later that he came to form
aesthetic views on the basis of utilitarian ones. It is labour that bears
the stamp of the aesthetic. In contrast to the activities of animals,
it is concerned with creative transformation of life. Animals create
unconsciously, by force of biological necessity and according to the
needs of the species they belong to. Building a dam, a beaver has no
preconceived plan of construction but acts instinctively. Man creates
consciously, first drawing up a plan and finally arriving at the result
which corresponds to his intention. Using the natural properties of
phenomena for his purpose he establishes himself in the world
through material and spiritual values produced by labour.
Karl Marx wrote, "An animal forms objects only in accordance with
the standard and the need of the species to which it belongs, whilst
man knows how to produce in accordance with the standard of every
species, and knows how to apply everywhere the inherent standard
to the object. Man therefore also forms objects in accordance with
the laws of beauty."2
What is then the measure which is inherent in the object? It is not
the natural laws which govern the development of matter organised
by the presence of an inner purpose, for nature does not have a
purpose. Carving La petite fee des eaux out of marble, Rodin did
not act according to the logical idea which marble as a natural
material possesses. No purposeful evolution of marble outside society
and human activity would be able to engender either a purpose or
measure that would allow a block of marble to become a sculpture
in the hands of man. Rodin created his piece by "cutting off
everything superfluous", which was a search for precisely that
inner measure of the natural material in its correlation to the social
needs of man. That block of marble could not have been used to
make a teaspoon or an ingot mould – in either case, the use of the
natural material would not have corresponded to its measure.
Measure is the result of the discovery by man, in the course of his
exploration of the world, of the object's inner potential for serving
man and satisfying his needs.
The Beautiful as a Positive Universal Human Value
Only those natural properties of an object engender beauty which
are correlated in the process of social production to man's needs and
are determined by the level of social development. Beauty is objective, for it depends not on its perception by an individual but
on the actual value of the object for man. This aesthetic quality is
social, for it is determined by production which involves the whole
world into the field of human activity and puts every object into a
certain relation to man. Thus beauty is the broadest positive social
significance of a phenomenon, its positive value for the human
race.
The beautiful does imply that an object has been "spiritualised",
but not by the Absolute Idea or an individual, but by society
and its productive activity. Social production has made nature"the non-organic body of man" and left a stamp of the personality
of modern man on the objects of the outside world; production has
turned this world into a real embodiment of man's essential powers.
Social production has embraced all the visible world; at present, all
its phenomena have either been transformed by man's activity which
has turned them into the "second nature", or are being explored, or
form the arsenal of man's future and more impressive power. No
phenomena exist which are of no consequence to society and are not
correlated to society. This is where the "spirituality" of phenomena
and their aesthetic qualities stem from. To make the world the
kingdom of beauty means to spiritualise and humanise it.
Finally, the beautiful is the realm of man's freedom. It is phenomena
which have been cognised and explored. They contain nothing
frightening or repulsive: man has mastered them and is therefore
free where his relationship with them is concerned. It should be
stressed that here, no personal rule over the phenomenon is implied
but only man's rule as a race, the rule determined by the
development of social production.
Beauty in the life of society is manifested in political and social
freedom; in nature – in man's free mastery over the object (the ability
to understand, master, create, make); and in art or sports in
possessing effortless skill.
Beauty is a product of history. The phenomena reflecting the
mastery of man over the material world which is maximal at a given
level of social development are considered beautiful. Free mastery
over the powers of nature and the knowledge how to make their
laws and properties serve a practical purpose give man high aesthetic
pleasure.
The sum total of the definitions given above is necessary and
sufficient for a characteristic of the nature and essence of the
beautiful as a key category of the aesthetics. It shows that there is
no difference of principle between the aesthetic properties of natural
and of social phenomena. In both cases, these properties have an
objective-material, social substance.
However, beauty in the life of society is the most complicated and
delicate matter. Here, "the crystal lattice" of a beautiful structure
is formed not by atoms but by people and their lives. It is no
accident that the most elevated realm of aesthetic cognition of the
world according to the laws of the beautiful is art as a social
phenomenon. It remakes the experience of life into beauty. No
matter whether the artist is concerned with suffering, heroic deeds,
ugliness or comic occurrences, his work is a source of aesthetic
delight.
Soren A. Kierkegaard, the 19th-century Danish philosopher, gave a
graphic characteristic of a poet: a deeply unhappy individual whose
heart is filled with suffering but whose lips are formed in such a way
that when a groan escapes them it turns into beautiful music. This
image is a new interpretation, as it were, of an old Greek legend.
The sculptor Perilles presented a tyrant with a gigantic bronze ox.
A man sentenced to death was placed inside it, and a fire was laid
under the belly of the monster. The ox's throat and mouth were
made in such a way that the agonised yells and groans of the dying
man were transformed into melodious sounds. By the way, one
of the first to die in this fashion was the sculptor himself.
The Greeks had a gift of turning everything into beauty. Their myths
are full of it. Even the Gods' revenge on Niobe is beautiful. However
horrible the occasion is, it assumes a beautiful form: the arrows
which killed her children are sunrays.
Beauty in art is perfection of form, depth of meaning, profound
knowledge of the subject, and the consequence of the artistic idea
conveyed by the work.
An accurate and impassive copying of life does not produce beauty.
The latter can be attained in art only by a creative approach to life."You are not a lowly copyist but a poet! " wrote Honore de Balzac."Otherwise the sculptor would have done his job by making a plaster
cast of a woman. Very well, try then to make a plaster cast of the
arm of the woman you love and place it before yourself – you
will see an arm of a corpse without the slightest resemblance to the
original, and will have to turn to a sculptor who, without producing
an exact replica, will reproduce motion and life. We must grasp the
spirit, the meaning, the characteristic shape of objects and beings."
Embodying the ideal of beauty, art awakens man's creative potential,
fosters his ability to find the inner measure of objects and correlate
their properties with his social needs, and teaches him to appreciate
beauty and create according to its laws.
1 This distinction between the useful and the beautiful is made by Socrates – a character in Plato's dialogue. In real life Socrates maintained that the useful is beautiful for that for which it is useful.
2 Karl Marx, "Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844", in: Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works, Vol.3, Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1975, p.277.
next